weak selection

Traulsen A 2010 Mathematics of kin and group selection: formally equivalent? Evolution 64:316-323.

  • the underlying mathematics of game theory is fundamentally different from the approach of inclusive fitness
  • does a single cooperator have a fixation probability larger than neutral in the system?
  • this would mean that cooperation can be called advantageous in a finite population
  • the thresholds based on fixation probabilities are global variables that take into account all possible frequencies of cooperators
  • these thresholds typically characterize the probabilities of the stochastic process, with each realization taking a different trajectory
  • the direction of selection is a deterministic local statement valid for a particular frequency and all trajectories
  • sometimes, such deterministic statements describe the average of a stochastic process
  • but in general this is not the case
  • evolutionary game theory is a general way to model frequency-dependent selection
  • in its modern finite population formulation (which is closely related to theoretical population genetics), stochastic effects are taken into account
  • recently, several authors have drawn insights from this new formulation
  • these models do not only consider group selection, but also selection in network structured populations or cooperation based on similarity
  • proponents of kin selection theory have argued that the results of these papers can equivalently be obtained from inclusive fitness methods (Lehmann and Keller 2006; Lehmann et al. 2007a,b; West et al. 2007b)
  • here, it is argued that this equivalence is in fact only found in special cases and that we are not facing a purely semantic question
  • many authors argue that the Price equation is the fundamental basis of evolutionary dynamics and provides the formal foundation for both kin selection and group selection
  • others have argued that this central role of the Price equation is misleading
  • to calculate the change of E(p), we have to know Cov(p, f)
  • this implies that we also need an equation that describes the change of Cov(p, f), involving terms such as Cov(fp, f)
  • the equation in Cov(fp, f) will again depend on higher moments of the distributions for f and p
  • only if such higher order moments can be expressed in terms of the lower moments, the system of equations becomes dynamically sufficient
  • the Price equation only allows to make a local statement on the direction and speed of evolution
  • this makes it impossible to calculate important evolutionary quantities, such as the probability of fixation
  • when selection is weak and fitness effects are additive, the direction and intensity of selection are constant
  • fixation probabilities can be assessed for finite populations with inclusive fitness methods
  • frequency-dependent selection per se is not a problem for inclusive fitness
  • it typically considers a special case of linear games in which the fitness differences are constant
  • with nonlinearities, inclusive fitness arguments can become wrong (van Veelen 2009)
  • for frequency-dependent selection, the seemingly small difference in the definition of weak selection has decisive mathematical consequences (Wild and Traulsen 2007)
  • Nowak et al. (2004) obtain interesting new results for nonadditive games under weak selection, such as the so-called one-third rule
  • the underlying definition of weak selection differs such that the conclusions are altered
  • when the phenotype space is continuous, the weak selection approach of inclusive fitness is appropriate
  • in discrete phenotype spaces, the game-theoretic approach can be more meaningful
  • why weak selection has to be invoked at all?
  • weak selection is invoked in kin selection approaches because the relatedness can usually be calculated only for neutral systems
  • under weak selection, the term describing selection factorizes into terms that depend on the payoff values and terms that invoke averages such as the probability to choose a pair of different individuals
  • the latter terms correspond to the relatedness, which can therefore be calculated under neutrality to assess first-order effects
  • combining this neutral relatedness with almost neutral weak selection allows to derive consequences of the evolutionary dynamics
  • such calculations are nontrivial and would become extremely challenging in the presence of selection
  • this is very similar to coalescence theory, which also focuses on the neutral case
  • for strong selection, we would have to depart from the reference case of neutral selection, because even a high order Taylor expansion is local and can only describe the dynamics close to the reference point
  • typically, one would assume that under strong selection some aspects of the dynamics become deterministic
  • in contrast, theoretical population genetics usually only requires weak selection to simplify equations, for example, by diffusion approximation
  • for some population structures, weak selection does not have to be invoked at all to make exact analytical statements
  • this is the case for the multilevel selection model discussed by Traulsen and Nowak (2006)
  • it is also true for evolutionary games on cycles, where players are arranged on a line (Ohtsuki and Nowak 2006a)
  • although weak selection seems to be relevant for genetic systems, when it comes to cultural evolution it may not be an appropriate approximation